The White
Ribbon Screening, University of Brighton,
15 April 2013
The subtitle
of the German release of Michael Haneke’s The
White Ribbon (2009) is ‘a German Children’s Story’, and the film is set in
a German village between 1913 and 1914. Clear enough. In an interview with Time Out Michael
Haneke insisted:
This kind of displacement – from a specific cultural context to a more general
context, or argument – is a signature of Haneke’s filmmaking. It is also, I’d
suggest, a problematic gesture. In the case of The White Ribbon it is hard to escape the fact that this probing of
childhood or teenage ‘fanaticism’ or ‘terrorism’ is highly-specific to the
generation that will bring forth Nazism. This, I think, is one of the central
equivocations of the film.
If we take a contextual
reading we can locate The White Ribbon
in the wider genre that probes the psychopathology of Nazism. In his
controversial two-volume work on the pathological fantasies of the Freikorps – the post-World War One
veterans groups – Klaus Theweleit also probed the structures of childhood that,
for him, conditioned the emergence of Nazism. This speaks to the context of The White Ribbon. Theweleit notes that: ‘The fascist
state needed, and this reinforced, the family in its capacity as ordering force
and ego boundary; but the family remained more or less an obstacle to the
fascist will to world domination.’ (1989: 252) The result was what he called
the ‘fascist double-bind’ (1989: 252) – the family as essential to the new
order and also, as in The White Ribbon,
a structure to be contested or exceeded. What we might call the inchoate
campaign of the children (if, in fact, the children are responsible, which is only heavily implied) in the film will later be canalized, we could assume, by the Nazi state, as ‘the child was
encouraged to take action against its parents as an informer in the service of
the Führer.’ (1989: 252)
Thewelheit’s analysis is remarkably
suggestive of the psychopathology probed by the film: ‘Their aim is to
annihilate what they perceive as absolute falsity and evil, in order to
regenerate their ego in a better world.’ (Theweleit 1989: 253) These are fanatics of the ‘good’, so to
speak, fanatics of the immanent and unfulfilled morality by which they are
abused and constrained. They ‘punish the sins of the father(s)’: the doctor, the Baron, the steward, and the pastor. Although we should add that in the case of the pastor this authority is not merely authoritatian, but a creepy combination of reasoned discourse and violence. It is this discourse the children turn against the fathers.
Eric Santner considers the
psychopathology of Nazism through the lens of the case of Daniel Paul Schreber,
the German jurist who fell into a paranoid psychosis after being elected to a
senior judicial role in 1884. For Santner this disorder is a result of a crisis
of investiture and Schreber’s psychosis provides an x-ray of the disorders of
Germany itself – Santner’s book is entitled My Own Private Germany. Drawing on Lacanian psychoanalysis, Santner suggests
that what is revealed is the perverse enjoyment (jouissance) at the heart of symbolic authority: ‘Schreber discovers
that symbolic authority in a state of emergency is transgressive, that it
exhibits an obscene overproximity to the subject: that it, as Schreber puts it,
demands enjoyment.’ (1997: 32)
Schreber’s ‘pathology’ reveals the raw matter of ideology before it is processed
or gentrified into official ideology. This raw state of ideology is the
galvanizing effect of enjoyment that ‘powers’ the ideological field.
We could link this to Haneke’s film,
as it probes a certain ‘crisis’ or ‘emergency’ in generational transmission
which generates what Santner calls a ‘sense of surreal corruption’ (1997: 43).
What Haneke implies is that the transgression of the children lies in their
extreme obedience, which, to continue with Santner, implies ‘getting too close to this [drive] dimension of
social reality.’ (Santner 1997: 43) Taking seriously Old Testament morality resutls from and produces a crisis in authority. This getting ‘too close’ produces the scenes
of ‘surreal corruption’ – sexual abuse, violence, disturbance – that emerge in
the film. This is realism turned studied and phantasmagoric.
Taking another contextual approach,
one not licensed by Haneke, we can also connect The White Ribbon, strangely perhaps, to the genre of the horror
film. More specifically we can connect this work, and other Haneke films
(especially Benny’s Video and Funny Games) to the horror genre of ‘the
terrible child’, or teenager. The literary terrible child emerges in works like
Tom Tyron’s The Other (1971) and Ira
Levin’s Rosemary’s Baby (1967), both
rapidly made into films.
Robin Wood argued that these films of
‘the terrible child’ are ambivalent: on the one hand, they are reactionary,
affirming the patriarchal family as bulwark against the ‘horror’ of the younger
generation. On the other hand, as in The
Omen (1978), they stage the extinction of this family (Wood 1986: 88). Wood
remarks, channelling Walter Benjamin, that ‘The
Omen would make no sense in a society that was not prepared to enjoy and
surreptitiously condone the working out of its own destruction.’ (1986: 88) It’s
striking that Robin Wood planned to write a book on Michael Haneke, but died in
1989, the same year as the release of The
White Ribbon. While Wood respected Haneke’s achievement the bathos of my
comparison of The White Ribbon with The Omen is intended to suggest the
problematic status of the ‘horror’ of the ‘terrible child’.
We could recall Omen II’s use of the military school as ambiguous structure of
authority – even trying the patience of the child of Satan. In The White Ribbon we can ponder this fear
of the child, especially if we follow Haneke’s generalising argument that it
might apply to all children, or all 'fanatical children'. This use of the idea of fanaticism (to follow
Alberto Toscano (2009)), risks the usual reactionary tropes of the fear of
abstraction and equality, as the children refuse to respect the ‘moral texture’
of the community. On the other hand, their attacks might seem well deserved,
bringing down this immoral ‘moral community’ by revealing and disrupting its
‘obscene underside’. The fathers burn with enjoyment, such as the doctors sexual abuse, but also the Baron's anger, pastor's hypocrisy, and steward negligence. The baronness notes this is a community of envy, apathy, and brutality. This is the equivocation that links to the equivocation of the terrible child film, which suggests it is not so original and equally problematic.
The generalization of the structure
of the fanatical child seems, to me, to end up in metaphysical problems. In a
laudatory discussion of the film John Orr remarks that ‘[Haneke’s] pessimism
about the human condition goes beyond its very specific Adornian incarnation –
the aphoristic savaging of commodity capitalism.’ (2011: 263) In this way we
fully detach from any context, and this is also evident in Orr’s claim, which I
don’t find convincing, that ‘Haneke has systematically uncoupled all the links
in the causal chain’ (Orr 2011: 261). The detachment of Haneke allows him to
generate a metaphysical thesis of evil, which both plays to the horrors of
Nazism and occludes them. At the same time it collapses together all
‘fanatical’ instances into a metaphysical refusal and evil that runs very close
to the ideological uses of the idea of fanaticism against any politics of
abstraction or equality. In doing so, of course, it becomes abstract in turn.
This, I think, is one of the puzzles
of the film. In many ways detailed and textured it is also abstract and
schematic, deliberately and at the same time. Haneke’s use of schematic
‘Brechtian’ character names and his use of back-and-white are, he points out,
deliberate ‘distancing’ and abstracting strategies. So, we have a
decontextualization that is supported aesthetically and by a practice of
metaphysical claim or abstraction.
What concerns me is not equivocation per se, but the tendecy and structure of how these equivocations fall in the film. The film is, at once, not abstract enough (in its particular but insufficient evocation of context) and too abstract (as it spirals into 'higher' levels of abstraction, all the way up to evil itself). It is not adequate as a thesis about Nazism, nor about generalised fanaticism. What it is perhaps best at is the resonance of its probing of abusive forms of power and control, the petty forms of authority, and Haneke's usual refusal to align 'correct' responses to events. But the floating forms here threaten to become attached to prenicious ideaological tropes and to push us not into autonomy, but into well worn anxieties concerning fanaticism and power. After all isn’t this just another horror film? But not even that, as this is a dishonest horror film.
What concerns me is not equivocation per se, but the tendecy and structure of how these equivocations fall in the film. The film is, at once, not abstract enough (in its particular but insufficient evocation of context) and too abstract (as it spirals into 'higher' levels of abstraction, all the way up to evil itself). It is not adequate as a thesis about Nazism, nor about generalised fanaticism. What it is perhaps best at is the resonance of its probing of abusive forms of power and control, the petty forms of authority, and Haneke's usual refusal to align 'correct' responses to events. But the floating forms here threaten to become attached to prenicious ideaological tropes and to push us not into autonomy, but into well worn anxieties concerning fanaticism and power. After all isn’t this just another horror film? But not even that, as this is a dishonest horror film.